Dictionary Definition
fallacious adj
1 containing or based on a fallacy; "fallacious
reasoning"; "an unsound argument" [syn: unsound]
2 intended to deceive; "deceitful advertising";
"fallacious testimony"; "smooth, shining, and deceitful as thin
ice" - S.T.Coleridge; "a fraudulent scheme to escape paying taxes"
[syn: deceitful,
fraudulent]
3 based on an incorrect or misleading notion or
information; "fallacious hope"
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Pronunciation
-
- Rhymes: -eɪʃəs
Adjective
- Characterized by fallacy; false or mistaken.
- Deceptive or misleading.
Translations
Characterized by fallacy; false or mistaken
- Dutch: bedrieglijk
- Finnish: virheellinen, paikkansapitämätön; (literary, poetic) erheellinen
- French: fallacieux
Deceptive or misleading
- Finnish: harhaanjohtava, pettävä, erehdyttävä
Extensive Definition
A fallacy is a component of an argument which, being
demonstrably flawed in its logic or form, renders the
argument invalid in
whole (except for begging the question fallacy, in which case the
argument is valid).
Types of fallacies
In logical arguments, fallacies are either formal or informal. Because the validity of a deductive argument depends on its form, a formal fallacy is a deductive argument that has an invalid form, whereas an informal fallacy is any other invalid mode of reasoning whose flaw is not in the form of the argument.Beginning with Aristotle,
informal fallacies have generally been placed in one of several
categories, depending on the source of the fallacy. There are
fallacies of relevance, fallacies involving causal reasoning, and
fallacies resulting from ambiguities (or equivocations). Most common
forms of fallacies are evident in political speeches.
Recognizing fallacies in actual arguments may be
difficult since arguments are often structured using rhetorical patterns that
obscure the logical connections between assertions. Fallacies may
also exploit the emotional or intellectual
weaknesses of the interlocutor. Having the
capability of recognizing logical fallacies in arguments reduces
the likelihood of such an occurrence.
A different approach to understanding and
classifying fallacies is provided by argumentation
theory; see for instance the van Eemeren, Grootendorst
reference below. In this approach, an argument is regarded as an
interactive protocol
between individuals which attempts to resolve a disagreement. The
protocol is regulated by certain rules of interaction, and
violations of these rules are fallacies. Many of the fallacies in
the list below are best understood as being fallacies in this
sense.
Fallacious arguments involve not only formal logic
but also causality.
Others involve psychological ploys such as use of power
relationships between proposer and interlocutor, appeals to
patriotism and morality, appeals to ego etc., to establish
necessary intermediate (explicit or implicit) premises for an
argument. Indeed, fallacies very often lie in unstated assumptions
or implied
premises in arguments that are not always obvious at first
glance.
Note that providing a critique of an argument has
no relation to the truth
of the conclusion.
The conclusion could very well be true, while the argument as to
why the conclusion is true is not valid. See argument
from fallacy.
Material fallacies
The classification of material fallacies widely
adopted by modern logicians and based on that of Aristotle,
Organon
(Sophistici
elenchi), is as follows:
- Fallacy of Accident (also called destroying the exception or a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid)--makes a generalization that disregards exceptions (e.g., Cutting people is a crime. Surgeons cut people. Therefore, surgeons are criminals.)
- Converse Fallacy of Accident (also called reverse accident, destroying the exception, or a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter)--argues from a special case to a general rule (e.g., If we allow people with glaucoma to use medicinal marijuana then everyone should be allowed to use marijuana.)
- Irrelevant
Conclusion (also called Ignoratio Elenchi)--diverts attention
away from a fact in dispute rather than address it directly. This
is sometimes referred to as a "red
herring". Subsets include:
- purely personal considerations (argumentum ad hominem),
- popular sentiment (argumentum ad populum--appeal to the majority),
- fear (argumentum ad baculum),
- conventional propriety (argumentum ad verecundiam--appeal to authority)
- Fallacy of the Consequent--draws a conclusion from premises that do not support that conclusion (e.g., If I have the flu, then I have a sore throat. I have a sore throat. Therefore, I have the flu. Other illnesses may cause sore throat.)
- Begging the question (also called Petitio Principii, Circulus in Probando--arguing in a circle, or assuming the answer)--demonstrates a conclusion by means of premises that assume that conclusion (e.g., We must institute the death penalty to discourage violent crime. This statement assumes the violent crime rate will fall when the death penalty is imposed.)
- Call to Perfection is committed when one argues to postpone some action or policy until some unlikely event or impossible change is achieved. (example: I'll do it the day that pigs can fly. Since pigs do not fly and will probably never be able to, the action or policy will probably never take place.)
- Fallacy
of False Cause or Non
Sequitur (Latin for "it does not follow")--incorrectly assumes
one thing is the cause of another (e.g., Our nation will prevail
because God is great.)
- A special case of this fallacy also goes by the Latin term post hoc ergo propter hoc--the fallacy of believing that temporal succession implies a causal relation.
- Another special case is given by the Latin term cum hoc ergo propter hoc -- the fallacy of believing that happenstance implies causal relation (aka as fallacy of causation versus correlation: assumes that correlation implies causation).
- Fallacy of Many Questions (Plurium Interrogationum)--groups more than one question in the form of a single question (e.g., Is it true that you no longer beat your wife? A yes or no answer will still be an admission of guilt to wife-beating.)
Example
James argues:
- Cheese is food.
- Food is delicious.
- Therefore, cheese is delicious.
This argument claims to prove that cheese is
delicious. This particular argument has the form of a categorical
syllogism. Any argument must have premises as well as a
conclusion. In this case we need to ask what the premises are—that
is, the set of assumptions the proposer of the argument can expect
the interlocutor to grant. The first assumption is almost true by
definition: cheese is a
foodstuff edible by humans. The second assumption is less clear as
to its meaning. Since the assertion has no quantifiers of any kind, it
could mean any one of the following:
- All food is delicious.
- Most food is delicious.
- To me, all food is delicious.
- Some food is delicious.
In all but the first interpretation,
the above syllogism would then fail to have validated its second
premise. James may try to assume that his interlocutor believes
that all food is delicious; if the interlocutor grants this then
the argument is valid. In this case, the interlocutor is
essentially conceding the point to James. However, the interlocutor
is more likely to believe that some food is disgusting, such as a
frog's liver white chocolate torte; and in this case James is not
much better off than he was before he formulated the argument,
since he now has to prove the assertion that cheese is a unique
type of universally delicious food, which is a disguised form of
the original thesis. From the point of view of the interlocutor,
James commits the logical fallacy of begging
the question.
Verbal fallacies
Verbal fallacies are those in which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words. They are generally classified as follows.- Equivocation consists in employing the same word in two or more senses, e.g. in a syllogism, the middle term being used in one sense in the major and another in the minor premise, so that in fact there are four not three terms ("All heavy things have a great mass; This is heavy fog; therefore this fog has a great mass").
- Connotation fallacies occur when a dysphemistic word is substituted for the speaker's actual quote and used to discredit the argument. It is a form of attribution fallacy.
- Amphibology is the result of ambiguity of grammatical structure, e.g. of the position of the adverb "only" in careless writers ("He only said that," in which sentence, the adverb has been intended to qualify any one of the other three words).
- Fallacy of Composition "From Each to All". Arguing from some property of constituent parts, to the conclusion that the composite item has that property e.g. "all the band members (constituent parts) are highly skilled, therefore the band (composite item) is highly skilled". This can be acceptable with certain arguments such as spatio arguments e.g. "all the parts of the car are in the garage, therefore the car is in the garage"
- Division, the converse of the preceding, arguing from a property of the whole, to each constituent part e.g. "the university (the whole) is 700 years old, therefore, all the staff (each part) are 700 years old".
- Proof by verbosity, sometimes colloquially referred to as argumentum verbosium - a rhetorical technique that tries to persuade by overwhelming those considering an argument with such a volume of material that the argument sounds plausible, superficially appears to be well-researched, and it is so laborious to untangle and check supporting facts that the argument might be allowed to slide by unchallenged.
- Accent, which occurs only in speaking and consists of emphasizing the wrong word in a sentence. e.g., "He is a fairly good pianist," according to the emphasis on the words, may imply praise of a beginner's progress, or an expert's deprecation of a popular hero, or it may imply that the person in question is a deplorable pianist.
- Figure of Speech, the confusion between the metaphorical and ordinary uses of a word or phrase.
- Fallacy of Misplaced Concretion, identified by Whitehead in his discussion of metaphysics, this refers to the reification of concepts which exist only in discourse.
Example 1
Barbara argues:- Andre is a good tennis player.
- Therefore, Andre is 'good', that is to say a morally good person.
Here the problem is that the word good
has different meanings, which is to say that it is an ambiguous word.
In the premise, Barbara says that Andre is good at some particular
activity, in this case tennis. In the conclusion, she says that
Andre is a morally good person. These are clearly two different
senses of the word "good". The premise might be true but the
conclusion can still be false: Andre might be the best tennis
player in the world but a rotten person morally. However, it is not
legitimate to infer he is a bad person on the ground there has been
a fallacious argument on the part of Barbara. Nothing concerning
Andre's moral qualities is to be inferred from the premise.
Appropriately, since it plays on an ambiguity, this sort of fallacy
is called the fallacy of equivocation, that is,
equating two incompatible terms or claims.
Example 2
Jason argues:
- Nothing is better than eternal happiness.
- Eating a hamburger is better than nothing.
- Therefore, eating a hamburger is better than eternal happiness.
This argument has the appearance of an inference
that applies transitivity
of the two-placed relation is better than, which in this critique
we grant is a valid property. The argument is an example of
syntactic ambiguity. In fact, the first premise semantically does
not predicate an attribute of the subject, as would for instance
the assertion
- A potato is better than eternal happiness.
In fact it is semantically equivalent to the
following universal
quantification:
- Everything fails to be better than eternal happiness.
So instantiating this fact with eating a
hamburger, it logically follows that
- Eating a hamburger fails to be better than eternal happiness.
Note that the premise A hamburger is better than
nothing does not provide anything to this argument. This fact
really means something such as
- Eating a hamburger is better than eating nothing at all.
Thus this is a fallacy
of composition.
These sort of fallacies are firmly tied to
English language and how the words are used in ambiguous ways in
several expressions. The phrase "nothing is better than X" actually
means "Such a thing that would be better than X does not exist". If
the arguments mentioned in this article were to be translated to
other languages, they would suddenly make no sense at all since the
word "nothing" would be translated differently in different
sentences.
Logical fallacy
The standard Aristotelian logical fallacies are:
- Fallacy of Four Terms (Quaternio terminorum)
- Fallacy of Undistributed Middle
- Fallacy of Illicit process of the major or the Illicit minor term;
- Fallacy of Negative Premises.
Other logical fallacies include:
In philosophy, the term logical
fallacy properly refers to a formal fallacy : a flaw in the
structure of a deductive
argument
which renders the argument invalid.
However, it is often used more generally in
informal discourse to mean an argument which is problematic for any
reason, and thus encompasses informal fallacies as well as formal
fallacies. – valid but unsound claims or bad
nondeductive argumentation – .
The presence of a formal fallacy in a deductive
argument does not imply anything about the argument's premises or
its conclusion (see fallacy
fallacy). Both may actually be true, or even more probable as a
result of the argument (e.g. appeal
to authority), but the deductive argument is still invalid
because the conclusion does not follow from the premises in the
manner described. By extension, an argument can contain a formal
fallacy even if the argument is not a deductive one; for instance
an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of
probability or
causality can be said
to commit a formal fallacy.
Example
In the strictest sense, a logical fallacy is the incorrect application of a valid logical principle or an application of a nonexistent principle:- Most Rimnars are Jornars.
- Most Jornars are Dimnars.
- Therefore, most Rimnars are Dimnars.
This is fallacious. And so is this:
- The average family has 2.5 children.
- The Smiths are a very average family.
- Therefore, the Smiths must have 2 or 3 children.
Indeed, there is no logical principle that
states:
- For some x, P(x).
- For some x, Q(x).
- Therefore for some x, P(x) and Q(x).
An easy way to show the above inference is
invalid is by using Venn
diagrams. In logical parlance, the inference is invalid, since
under at least one interpretation of the predicates it is not
validity preserving.
Other systems of classification
Of other classifications of fallacies in general the most famous are those of Francis Bacon and J. S. Mill. Bacon (Novum Organum, Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone. With these should be compared the Offendicula of Roger Bacon, contained in the Opus maius, pt. i. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book v. of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks. See Rd. Whateley's Logic, bk. v.; A. de Morgan, Formal Logic (1847) ; A. Sidgwick, Fallacies (1883) and other textbooks.Fallacies in the media and politics
"Either you're for me, or against me" unknown but
common fallacy (False dilemma).
Fallacies are used frequently by pundits
in the media and
politics. When one
politician says to another, "You don't have the moral authority to
say X", this could be an example of the argumentum ad
hominem or personal
attack fallacy; that is, attempting to disprove X, not by
addressing validity of X but by attacking the person who asserted
X. Arguably, the politician is not even attempting to make an
argument against X, but is instead offering a moral rebuke against
the interlocutor. For instance, if X is the assertion:
- The military uniform is a symbol of national strength and honor.
Then ostensibly, the politician is not trying to
prove the contrary assertion. If this is the case, then there is no
logically fallacious argument, but merely a personal opinion about
moral worth. Thus identifying logical fallacies may be difficult
and dependent upon context.
In the opposite direction is the fallacy of
argument
from authority. A classic example is the ipse dixit—"He
himself said it" argument—used throughout the Middle Ages
in reference to Aristotle. A
modern instance is "celebrity spokespersons" in advertisements: a
product is good and you should buy/use/support it because your
favorite celebrity endorses it.
An appeal to authority is always a logical
fallacy, though it can be an appropriate form of rational argument if, for
example, it is an appeal to expert
testimony . In this case, the expert witness must be recognized
as such and all parties must agree that the testimony is
appropriate to the circumstances. This form of argument is common
in legal situations.
By definition, arguments with logical fallacies
are invalid, but they
can often be (re)written in such a way that they fit a valid
argument
form. The challenge to the interlocutor is, of course, to
discover the false
premise, i.e. the premise that makes the argument unsound.
References
- Aristotle, On Sophistical Refutations, De Sophistici Elenchi.
- William of Ockham, Summa of Logic (ca. 1323) Part III.4.
- John Buridan, Summulae de dialectica Book VII.
- Francis Bacon, the doctrine of the idols in Novum Organum Scientiarum, Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man, XXIIIff.
- The Art of Controversy | Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten - The Art Of Controversy (bilingual), by Arthur Schopenhauer (also known as "Schopenhauers 38 stratagems")
- John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic - Raciocinative and Inductive. Book 5, Chapter 7, Fallacies of Confusion.
- C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies. Methuen London, 1970.
- Fearnside, W. Ward and William B. Holther, Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument, 1959.
- Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, ISBN 87-991013-7-8
- D. H. Fischer, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought, Harper Torchbooks, 1970.
- Douglas N. Walton, Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, 1989.
- F. H. van Eemeren and R. Grootendorst, Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies: A Pragma-Dialectical Perspective, Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 1992.
- Warburton Nigel, Thinking from A to Z, Routledge 1998.
- T. Edward Damer. Attacking Faulty Reasoning, 5th Edition, Wadsworth, 2005. ISBN 0-534-60516-8
- Sagan, Carl, "The Demon-Haunted World: Science As a Candle in the Dark". Ballantine Books, March 1997 ISBN 0-345-40946-9, 480 pgs. 1996 hardback edition: Random House, ISBN 0-394-53512-X, xv+457 pages plus addenda insert (some printings). Ch.12.
External links
portalpar Logic- Logical Fallacies.Info
- Stephen Downes Guide to the Logical Fallacies
- Logical Fallacies and the Art of Debate
- 42 informal logical fallacies explained by Dr. Michael C. Labossiere, including examples.
- List of fallacies with easy to understand examples.
- Fallacy files contains categorization of fallacies with examples.
fallacious in Arabic: سفسطة
fallacious in Min Nan: Lô-chek gō͘-biū
fallacious in Catalan: Fal·làcia
fallacious in Czech: Logický klam
fallacious in German: Fehlschluss
fallacious in Modern Greek (1453-): Λογική
πλάνη
fallacious in Spanish: Falacia
fallacious in Persian: سفسطه
fallacious in French: Sophisme
fallacious in Hindi: मिथ्या तर्क
fallacious in Indonesian: Kesesatan
fallacious in Icelandic: Rökvilla
fallacious in Italian: Fallacia
fallacious in Hebrew: כשל לוגי
fallacious in Lithuanian: Argumentacijos
klaida
fallacious in Hungarian: Érvelési hiba
fallacious in Dutch: Drogreden
fallacious in Japanese: 誤謬
fallacious in Norwegian: Tankefeil
fallacious in Polish: Sofizmat
fallacious in Portuguese: Falácia
fallacious in Simple English: Fallacy
fallacious in Slovak: Logický klam
fallacious in Serbian: Логичка грешка
fallacious in Finnish: Argumentointivirhe
fallacious in Swedish: Argumentationsfel
fallacious in Turkish: Safsata
fallacious in Ukrainian: Логічна хиба
fallacious in Chinese: 謬論
fallacious in Contenese: 謬論
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
Albigensian, Arian, Barmecidal, Barmecide, Catharist, Donatist, Ebionitist, Erastian, Gnostic, Jansenist, Jansenistic, Jovinianist, Jovinianistic, Lollard, Manichaean, Monophysite, Monophysitic, Montanist, Montanistic, Pelagian, Sabellian, Waldensian, Wyclifite, aberrant, abroad, absonant, adrift, airy, all abroad, all off, all
wrong, amiss, antinomian, apocryphal, apparent, apparently sound,
apparitional,
askew, astray, at fault, autistic, awry, beguiling, beside the mark,
casuistic, catchy, chimeric, colorable, contradictory, contrary to
fact, contrary to reason, corrupt, deceiving, deceptive, defective, deluding, delusional, delusionary, delusive, delusory, dereistic, deviant, deviational, deviative, disingenuous, distorted, dreamlike, dreamy, dubious, emanationist, empty, errant, erring, erroneous, false, fantastic, faultful, faulty, fishy, flawed, hallucinatory, heretical, heterodox, hollow, hylotheist, hylotheistic, illogical, illusional, illusionary, illusive, illusory, imaginary, in error, inauthentic, inconclusive, incongruous, inconsequent, inconsequential,
inconsistent,
insincere, invalid, irrational, jesuitic, loose, mad, misleading, nonorthodox, nonrational, nonscientific, not
following, not right, not true, off, off the track, ostensible, out, overrefined, oversubtle, pantheist, pantheistic, paralogical, peccant, perverse, perverted, phantasmagoric, phantasmal, phantom, philosophistic, plausible, questionable, reasonless, seeming, self-annulling,
self-contradictory, self-deceptive, self-deluding, self-refuting,
senseless, sophistic, sophistical, specious, spectral, straying, supposititious, trickish, tricksy, tricky, truthless, unaccepted, unactual, unapproved, unauthentic, unauthoritative,
uncanonical,
unconnected,
unfactual, unfounded, unorthodox, unphilosophical,
unproved, unreal, unreasonable, unscientific, unscriptural, unsound, unsubstantial, untrue, visionary, wide, without reason, wrong